Skip to content
  • Categories
  • Recent
  • Tags
  • Popular
  • Users
  • Groups
Skins
  • Light
  • Cerulean
  • Cosmo
  • Flatly
  • Journal
  • Litera
  • Lumen
  • Lux
  • Materia
  • Minty
  • Morph
  • Pulse
  • Sandstone
  • Simplex
  • Sketchy
  • Spacelab
  • United
  • Yeti
  • Zephyr
  • Dark
  • Cyborg
  • Darkly
  • Quartz
  • Slate
  • Solar
  • Superhero
  • Vapor

  • Default (No Skin)
  • No Skin
Collapse

The New Coffee Room

  1. TNCR
  2. General Discussion
  3. Puzzle time - two integers

Puzzle time - two integers

Scheduled Pinned Locked Moved General Discussion
20 Posts 4 Posters 156 Views
  • Oldest to Newest
  • Newest to Oldest
  • Most Votes
Reply
  • Reply as topic
Log in to reply
This topic has been deleted. Only users with topic management privileges can see it.
  • jon-nycJ Offline
    jon-nycJ Offline
    jon-nyc
    wrote on last edited by
    #1

    Of two unknown integers between 2 and 99, Leibniz is told the product and Newton is told the sum.

    The following conversation happens.

    Leibniz: “I don’t know the numbers.

    Newton: “I knew that.”

    Leibniz: “If that’s the case then I do know them.”

    Newton: “If that’s the case, so do I.”

    What are the two numbers? Prove your solution is unique.

    Only non-witches get due process.

    • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
    1 Reply Last reply
    • KlausK Offline
      KlausK Offline
      Klaus
      wrote on last edited by
      #2

      Could you change the story such that Leibniz "wins" in some meaningful way in the end?

      In the English-speaking world, Newton is always celebrated as the inventor of calculus, although Leibniz' contributions were more significant and influential. He deserves to kick Newton's ass.

      jon-nycJ 1 Reply Last reply
      • KlausK Klaus

        Could you change the story such that Leibniz "wins" in some meaningful way in the end?

        In the English-speaking world, Newton is always celebrated as the inventor of calculus, although Leibniz' contributions were more significant and influential. He deserves to kick Newton's ass.

        jon-nycJ Offline
        jon-nycJ Offline
        jon-nyc
        wrote on last edited by jon-nyc
        #3

        @klaus Is this better?

        Leibniz: “I don’t know the numbers.

        Newton: “I knew that.”

        Leibniz: “If even you knew that, then I definitely know them. Bitch.”

        Newton: “If that’s the case, so do I.”

        Leibniz: “So we both have intimate knowledge of them. Like your fucking sister”.

        Only non-witches get due process.

        • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
        1 Reply Last reply
        • AxtremusA Offline
          AxtremusA Offline
          Axtremus
          wrote on last edited by
          #4

          Can the “two unknown integers” be the same, or must they be different?

          jon-nycJ 1 Reply Last reply
          • AxtremusA Axtremus

            Can the “two unknown integers” be the same, or must they be different?

            jon-nycJ Offline
            jon-nycJ Offline
            jon-nyc
            wrote on last edited by
            #5

            @axtremus

            You'll have to decide.

            Only non-witches get due process.

            • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
            1 Reply Last reply
            • KlausK Offline
              KlausK Offline
              Klaus
              wrote on last edited by
              #6

              This is what I'm talking about.

              alt text

              If you laugh you are guilty.

              1 Reply Last reply
              • AxtremusA Offline
                AxtremusA Offline
                Axtremus
                wrote on last edited by
                #7

                ||2 and 3
                Had it been 2 and 2, both men would know immediately as both would be told 4 as the product and the sum.
                They had to go through one round of them “don’t knowing” to rule out 2 and 2.
                The answers are “small enough” such that immediately in the the next round, one guy “knows” right after ruling out 2 and 2. That leaves 2 and 3.
                ||

                jon-nycJ 1 Reply Last reply
                • AxtremusA Axtremus

                  ||2 and 3
                  Had it been 2 and 2, both men would know immediately as both would be told 4 as the product and the sum.
                  They had to go through one round of them “don’t knowing” to rule out 2 and 2.
                  The answers are “small enough” such that immediately in the the next round, one guy “knows” right after ruling out 2 and 2. That leaves 2 and 3.
                  ||

                  jon-nycJ Offline
                  jon-nycJ Offline
                  jon-nyc
                  wrote on last edited by
                  #8

                  @axtremus

                  With those numbers Newton would have known from the sum alone.

                  Only non-witches get due process.

                  • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
                  jon-nycJ AxtremusA 2 Replies Last reply
                  • jon-nycJ jon-nyc

                    @axtremus

                    With those numbers Newton would have known from the sum alone.

                    jon-nycJ Offline
                    jon-nycJ Offline
                    jon-nyc
                    wrote on last edited by jon-nyc
                    #9

                    Sorry Klaus - even Newton would have known. That idiot.

                    Only non-witches get due process.

                    • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
                    1 Reply Last reply
                    • jon-nycJ jon-nyc

                      @axtremus

                      With those numbers Newton would have known from the sum alone.

                      AxtremusA Offline
                      AxtremusA Offline
                      Axtremus
                      wrote on last edited by
                      #10

                      @jon-nyc said in Puzzle time - two integers:

                      @axtremus

                      With those numbers Newton would have known from the sum alone.

                      ||OK, 3 and 4 then.
                      No ambiguity with 3 and 3.
                      But enough ambiguity with 3 and 4.||

                      jon-nycJ 1 Reply Last reply
                      • AxtremusA Axtremus

                        @jon-nyc said in Puzzle time - two integers:

                        @axtremus

                        With those numbers Newton would have known from the sum alone.

                        ||OK, 3 and 4 then.
                        No ambiguity with 3 and 3.
                        But enough ambiguity with 3 and 4.||

                        jon-nycJ Offline
                        jon-nycJ Offline
                        jon-nyc
                        wrote on last edited by jon-nyc
                        #11

                        @axtremus

                        How would step 3 (of the 4 part conversation) have come about? IOW, how would learning that Newton knew (step 2) be sufficient for Leibniz to figure it out?

                        Only non-witches get due process.

                        • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
                        1 Reply Last reply
                        • KlausK Offline
                          KlausK Offline
                          Klaus
                          wrote on last edited by Klaus
                          #12

                          :::

                          4 and 13.

                          I wrote a little Scala program that contains the logic.
                          2cd03b91-32dd-4258-9dd3-49a8d39c5106-image.png
                          :::

                          1 Reply Last reply
                          • KlausK Offline
                            KlausK Offline
                            Klaus
                            wrote on last edited by Klaus
                            #13

                            :::

                            Interestingly, there is a unique solution even if the range of possible numbers is extended up to 865. At 866, the pair 4 and 61 shows up as another candidate.

                            :::

                            1 Reply Last reply
                            • jon-nycJ Offline
                              jon-nycJ Offline
                              jon-nyc
                              wrote on last edited by
                              #14

                              Klaus you got the answer but sorta cheating.

                              Care to try w/o code? It’s pretty satisfying. Elegant even.

                              Only non-witches get due process.

                              • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
                              1 Reply Last reply
                              • jon-nycJ Offline
                                jon-nycJ Offline
                                jon-nyc
                                wrote on last edited by jon-nyc
                                #15

                                @Axtremus

                                Why not approach it this way:

                                What are the implications of statement 1 by itself? How does statement 2 further constrain the possible answers? Etc.

                                This is definitely easier than trying pairs and seeing if the conversation rules them out.

                                Only non-witches get due process.

                                • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
                                1 Reply Last reply
                                • KlausK Offline
                                  KlausK Offline
                                  Klaus
                                  wrote on last edited by Klaus
                                  #16

                                  I assume you can reason about prime factor decompositions. For instance, if (and only if) the product decomposes into two prime numbers, or if one of the prime factors is > 50, then the product determines the two factors. I assume similar arguments can be made about the other statements such that the two numbers can eventually be derived analytically.

                                  Too lazy to do that now, though. Never think if you can let the computer do the work 😉

                                  1 Reply Last reply
                                  • NunataxN Offline
                                    NunataxN Offline
                                    Nunatax
                                    wrote on last edited by
                                    #17

                                    Something like this?
                                    All possible sums leading to Newton’s number consist of two numbers leading to a product that has at least two solutions under the given conditions (otherwise he can’t be sure that Leibniz does not know the 2 numbers). If the possible numbers leading to Leibniz’ product have only one such possible combination for the sum, then Newton’s remark leads to Leibniz knowing the numbers.

                                    If that’s correct, just give me a year or 50 to figure out the math formula to find the solution 😅

                                    1 Reply Last reply
                                    • jon-nycJ Offline
                                      jon-nycJ Offline
                                      jon-nyc
                                      wrote on last edited by jon-nyc
                                      #18

                                      Yes, @Nunatax that's spot on.

                                      First lets look at what we learn by each statement.

                                      From the first statement, (Leibniz saying he doesn't know x and y from P) we can infer that P isn't the product of 2 primes, and that it isn't the product a a prime above 50 and another number.

                                      From the second statement (Newton saying he knew Leibniz wouldn't know), we can infer that the sum is a number that cannot be expressed as the sum of two primes. Due to Goldbach's conjecture, we eliminate all of the positive numbers as potential sums, and any odd number that can be expressed as 'prime + 2'.

                                      This leaves us with the set I'll call S0 (that’s S zero):

                                      S0 = {11,17,23,27,29,35,37,41,47,51,53}

                                      Now the third statement, Leibniz knows the answer. That means the product P can only be factored into a single pair x,y such that x+y is an element of S0. For example, the product isn't 30, because both (2,15) and (6,5) sum to elements of S0. But the product could be (say) 18, because of the possible factor pairs (2,9), (3,6) only one of them sums to a member of S0. I'll need shorthand for this below, so let's call a product 'decidable by Leibniz' if it has this property.

                                      Now the 4th statement. Newton says "Now that I've know you know the answer, I know it, too". This means that, of all the (qualifying - ie between 2-99) pairs x,y that sum to S, only one of them is 'decidable by Leibniz'.

                                      So here you might think you need to look at every possible (qualifying) pair that sums to one of those 11 numbers in S0, find it's product, and see whether it is 'decidable by Leibniz', and then track which element in S0 has only one such pair. Lots of work.

                                      But there's a clever shortcut that lets us eliminate most of the elements of S0.

                                      Any element of S0 that can be expressed in multiple ways as a prime number + a multiple of 2 is automatically ruled out. Why? Remember that every element of S0 is odd, so any pair x,y must contain an even and an odd number. But if a number is (prime + multiple of 2) there's only one way to express it as the product of an even and odd number. So necessarily it can't have 2 factor pairs that sum to an element of S0, so it is what we called above 'decidable by Leibniz'. If an element of S0 can be expressed in multiple ways as (prime+multiple of 2) then it is it has multiple pairs 'decidable by Leibniz' and therefor cannot be 'decidable by Newton' in the last step of the conversation.

                                      We can therefore rule out the following:

                                      11 (as it equals 4+7 and 8+3)
                                      23 (as it equals 4+19 and 16+7)
                                      27 (as it equals 4+23 and 8+19)
                                      35 (as it equals 4+31 and 16+19)
                                      37 (as it equals 8+29 and 32+5)
                                      47 (as it equals 4+43 and 16+31)
                                      51 (as it equals 4+47 and 8+43)

                                      Which leaves us with S1={17, 29, 41, 53}

                                      Ok, now we have to do some calculations. Start with 17. It has 7 qualifying pairs that sum to it. We'll look at each and see if the pair would be 'decidable by Leibniz':

                                      2,15 not decideable by Leibniz, because 6 * 5 also 30 and also sums to an element of S0 (11)
                                      3,14 not decideable by Leibniz, because 2 * 21 also 42 and also sums to an element of S0 (23)
                                      4,13 decideable by Leibniz
                                      5,12 not decideable by Leibniz, because 3 * 20 also 60 and also sums to an element of S0 (23)
                                      6,11 not decideable by Leibniz, because 2 * 33 also 66 and also sums to an element of S0 (35)
                                      7,10 not decideable by Leibniz, because 2 * 35 also 70 and also sums to an element of S0 (37)
                                      8,9 not decideable by Leibniz, because 3 * 24 also 72 and also sums to an element of S0 (27)

                                      So we have an answer. x,y = (4,13)

                                      Is it unique? You might think we have to do the same exercise we just did for 17 with 29, 41, and 53 which have far more pairs and therefore would be far more tedious. But you don't need to look at all pairs, just find 2 that are 'decidable by Leibniz'. Remember we already have a shortcut to finding one that is 'decidable by Leibniz', namely a prime + a multiple of 2. We only need to poke around to find one more.

                                      If you do that you get (one possible answer anyway):

                                      29: (16, 13) and (4,25) are both 'decidable by Leibniz'
                                      41: (4,37) and (3,38) are both 'decidable by Leibniz'
                                      53: (6,47) and (16,37) are both 'decidable by Leibniz'

                                      So our original answer pair 4,13 is unique.

                                      Only non-witches get due process.

                                      • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
                                      KlausK 1 Reply Last reply
                                      • jon-nycJ jon-nyc

                                        Yes, @Nunatax that's spot on.

                                        First lets look at what we learn by each statement.

                                        From the first statement, (Leibniz saying he doesn't know x and y from P) we can infer that P isn't the product of 2 primes, and that it isn't the product a a prime above 50 and another number.

                                        From the second statement (Newton saying he knew Leibniz wouldn't know), we can infer that the sum is a number that cannot be expressed as the sum of two primes. Due to Goldbach's conjecture, we eliminate all of the positive numbers as potential sums, and any odd number that can be expressed as 'prime + 2'.

                                        This leaves us with the set I'll call S0 (that’s S zero):

                                        S0 = {11,17,23,27,29,35,37,41,47,51,53}

                                        Now the third statement, Leibniz knows the answer. That means the product P can only be factored into a single pair x,y such that x+y is an element of S0. For example, the product isn't 30, because both (2,15) and (6,5) sum to elements of S0. But the product could be (say) 18, because of the possible factor pairs (2,9), (3,6) only one of them sums to a member of S0. I'll need shorthand for this below, so let's call a product 'decidable by Leibniz' if it has this property.

                                        Now the 4th statement. Newton says "Now that I've know you know the answer, I know it, too". This means that, of all the (qualifying - ie between 2-99) pairs x,y that sum to S, only one of them is 'decidable by Leibniz'.

                                        So here you might think you need to look at every possible (qualifying) pair that sums to one of those 11 numbers in S0, find it's product, and see whether it is 'decidable by Leibniz', and then track which element in S0 has only one such pair. Lots of work.

                                        But there's a clever shortcut that lets us eliminate most of the elements of S0.

                                        Any element of S0 that can be expressed in multiple ways as a prime number + a multiple of 2 is automatically ruled out. Why? Remember that every element of S0 is odd, so any pair x,y must contain an even and an odd number. But if a number is (prime + multiple of 2) there's only one way to express it as the product of an even and odd number. So necessarily it can't have 2 factor pairs that sum to an element of S0, so it is what we called above 'decidable by Leibniz'. If an element of S0 can be expressed in multiple ways as (prime+multiple of 2) then it is it has multiple pairs 'decidable by Leibniz' and therefor cannot be 'decidable by Newton' in the last step of the conversation.

                                        We can therefore rule out the following:

                                        11 (as it equals 4+7 and 8+3)
                                        23 (as it equals 4+19 and 16+7)
                                        27 (as it equals 4+23 and 8+19)
                                        35 (as it equals 4+31 and 16+19)
                                        37 (as it equals 8+29 and 32+5)
                                        47 (as it equals 4+43 and 16+31)
                                        51 (as it equals 4+47 and 8+43)

                                        Which leaves us with S1={17, 29, 41, 53}

                                        Ok, now we have to do some calculations. Start with 17. It has 7 qualifying pairs that sum to it. We'll look at each and see if the pair would be 'decidable by Leibniz':

                                        2,15 not decideable by Leibniz, because 6 * 5 also 30 and also sums to an element of S0 (11)
                                        3,14 not decideable by Leibniz, because 2 * 21 also 42 and also sums to an element of S0 (23)
                                        4,13 decideable by Leibniz
                                        5,12 not decideable by Leibniz, because 3 * 20 also 60 and also sums to an element of S0 (23)
                                        6,11 not decideable by Leibniz, because 2 * 33 also 66 and also sums to an element of S0 (35)
                                        7,10 not decideable by Leibniz, because 2 * 35 also 70 and also sums to an element of S0 (37)
                                        8,9 not decideable by Leibniz, because 3 * 24 also 72 and also sums to an element of S0 (27)

                                        So we have an answer. x,y = (4,13)

                                        Is it unique? You might think we have to do the same exercise we just did for 17 with 29, 41, and 53 which have far more pairs and therefore would be far more tedious. But you don't need to look at all pairs, just find 2 that are 'decidable by Leibniz'. Remember we already have a shortcut to finding one that is 'decidable by Leibniz', namely a prime + a multiple of 2. We only need to poke around to find one more.

                                        If you do that you get (one possible answer anyway):

                                        29: (16, 13) and (4,25) are both 'decidable by Leibniz'
                                        41: (4,37) and (3,38) are both 'decidable by Leibniz'
                                        53: (6,47) and (16,37) are both 'decidable by Leibniz'

                                        So our original answer pair 4,13 is unique.

                                        KlausK Offline
                                        KlausK Offline
                                        Klaus
                                        wrote on last edited by
                                        #19

                                        @jon-nyc said in Puzzle time - two integers:

                                        Due to Goldbach's conjecture

                                        We all know how much I love to nitpick, hence let me point out that you don't need the Goldbach conjecture. Your method would work even if the conjecture turns out to be false.

                                        jon-nycJ 1 Reply Last reply
                                        • KlausK Klaus

                                          @jon-nyc said in Puzzle time - two integers:

                                          Due to Goldbach's conjecture

                                          We all know how much I love to nitpick, hence let me point out that you don't need the Goldbach conjecture. Your method would work even if the conjecture turns out to be false.

                                          jon-nycJ Offline
                                          jon-nycJ Offline
                                          jon-nyc
                                          wrote on last edited by
                                          #20

                                          @klaus

                                          True. Let’s say instead “due to all the work done to explore whether Goldbach’s Conjecture is true or not, we can safely say that...”

                                          Since Goldbach’s conjecture has been verified up to ~10^18, and we only need it to hold up to 198, that should work. 🙂

                                          Only non-witches get due process.

                                          • Cotton Mather, Salem Massachusetts, 1692
                                          1 Reply Last reply
                                          Reply
                                          • Reply as topic
                                          Log in to reply
                                          • Oldest to Newest
                                          • Newest to Oldest
                                          • Most Votes


                                          • Login

                                          • Don't have an account? Register

                                          • Login or register to search.
                                          • First post
                                            Last post
                                          0
                                          • Categories
                                          • Recent
                                          • Tags
                                          • Popular
                                          • Users
                                          • Groups